When business
people speak about “business ethics” they usually mean one of three things: (1)
avoid breaking the criminal law in one’s work-related activity; (2) avoid
action that may result in civil law suits against the company; and (3) avoid
actions that are bad for the company image. Businesses are especially concerned
with these three things since they involve loss of money and company
reputation. In theory, a business could address these three concerns by
assigning corporate attorneys and public relations experts to escort employees
on their daily activities. Anytime an employee might stray from the straight
and narrow path of acceptable conduct, the experts would guide him back.
Obviously this solution would be a financial disaster if carried out in
practice since it would cost a business more in attorney and public relations
fees than they would save from proper employee conduct. Perhaps reluctantly,
businesses turn to philosophers to instruct employees on becoming “moral.” For
over 2,000 years philosophers have systematically addressed the issue of right
and wrong conduct. Presumably, then, philosophers can teach employees a basic
understanding of morality will keep them out of trouble.
However,
it is not likely that philosophers can teach anyone to be ethical. The job of
teaching morality rests squarely on the shoulders of parents and one’s early
social environment. By the time philosophers enter the picture, it is too late
to change the moral predispositions of an adult. Also, even if philosophers
could teach morality, their recommendations are not always the most financially
efficient. Although being moral may save a company from some legal and public
relations nightmares, morality in business is also costly. A morally
responsible company must pay special attention to product safety, environmental
impact, truthful advertising, scrupulous marketing, and humane working
conditions. This may be more than a tight-budgeted business bargained for.
We
cannot easily resolve this tension between the ethical interests of the
money-minded businessperson and the ideal-minded philosopher. In most issues of
business ethics, ideal moral principles will be checked by economic viability.
To understand what is at stake, we will look at three different ways of
deriving standards of business ethics.
Deriving Business
Ethics from the Profit Motive. Some businesspeople argue that there
is a symbiotic relation between ethics and business in which ethics naturally
emerges from a profit-oriented business. There are both weak and strong
versions of this approach. The weak version is often expressed in the dictum
that good ethics results in good business, which simply means that moral
businesses practices are profitable. For example, it is profitable to make safe
products since this will reduce product liability lawsuits. Similarly, it may
be in the best financial interests of businesses to respect employee privacy,
since this will improve morale and thus improve work efficiency. Robert F.
Hartley's book, Business Ethics, takes this approach. Using 20 case studies as
illustrations, Hartley argues that the long-term best interests of businesses
are served by seeking a trusting relation with the public (Hartley, 1993). This
weak version, however, has problems. First, many moral business practices will
have an economic advantage only in the long run. This provides little incentive
for businesses that are designed to exclusively to seek short-term profits. As
more and more businesses compete for the same market, short-term profits will
dictate the decisions of many companies simply as a matter of survival. Second,
some moral business practices may not be economically viable even in the long
run. For example, this might be the case with retaining older workers who are
inefficient, as opposed to replacing them with younger and more efficient
workers. Third, and most importantly, those moral business practices that are
good for business depend upon what at that time will produce a profit. In a
different market, the same practices might not be economically viable. Thus,
any overlap that exists between morality and profit is both limited and
incidental.
The
strong version of this profit approach takes a reverse strategy and maintains
that, in a competitive and free market, the profit motive will in fact bring
about a morally proper environment. That is, if customers demand safe products,
or workers demand privacy, then they will buy from or work for only those
businesses that meet their demands. Businesses that do not heed these demands
will not survive. Since this view maintains that the drive for profit will
create morality, the strong version can be expressed in the dictum that good
business results in good ethics, which is the converse of the above dictum.
Proponents of this view, such as Milton Friedman, argue that this would happen
in the United States if the government would allow a truly competitive and free
market. But this strong view also has problems, since it assumes that consumers
or workers will demand the morally proper thing. In fact, consumers may opt for
less safe products if they know they will be saving money. For example,
consumers might prefer a cheaper car without air bags, even though doing so
places their own lives and the lives of their passengers at greater risk, which
is morally irresponsible. Similarly, workers may forego demands of privacy at
work if they are compensated with high enough wages. In short, not every moral
business practice will simply emerge from the profit principle as suggested by
either the weak or strong views.
Business Ethics
Restricted to Following the Law. A second approach to business ethics
is that moral obligations in business are restricted to what the law requires.
The most universal aspects of Western morality have already been put into our
legal system, such as with laws against killing, stealing, fraud, harassment,
or reckless endangerment. Moral principles beyond what the law requires – or
supra-legal principles -- appear to be
optional since philosophers dispute about their validity and society wavers
about its acceptance. For any specific issue under consideration, such as determining
what counts as responsible marketing or adequate privacy in the workplace, we
will find opposing positions on our supra-legal moral obligations. It is,
therefore, unreasonable to expect businesses to perform duties about which
there is so much disagreement and which appear to be optional.
The unreasonableness of such a moral
requirement in our society becomes all the more evident when we consider
societies that do have a strong external source of morality. Islam, for
example, contains a broad range of moral requirements such as an alms mandate,
prohibitions against sleeping partners that collect unearned money, and
restrictions on charging interest for certain types of loans, particularly for
relief aid. Thus, in Muslim countries that are not necessarily ruled by Islamic
law, there is a strong source of external morality that would be binding on
Muslim businesses apart from what their laws would require. Similarly,
Confucianism has a strong emphasis on filial piety; thus, in Chinese and other
Confucian societies, it is reasonable to expect their businesses to maintain a
respect for elders even if it is not part of the legal system. In Western
culture, or at least in the United States, we lack a counterpart to an external
source of morality as is present in Muslim or Confucian societies. One reason
is because of our cultural pluralism and the presence of a wide range of belief
systems. Even within Christianity, the diversity of denominations and beliefs
prevents it from being a homogeneous source of Christian values. In short,
without a widely recognized system of ethics that is external to the law,
supra-legal moral obligations in our society appear to be optional; and, it is
unreasonable to expect business people to be obligated to principles which
appear to be optional.
In
our culturally pluralistic society, the only business-related moral obligations
that are majority-endorsed by our national social group are those obligations
that are already contained in the law. These include a range of guidelines for
honesty in advertising, product safety, safe working conditions, and fair
hiring and firing practices. In fact, the unifying moral force of businesses
within our diverse society is the law itself. Beyond the law we find that the
moral obligations of businesses are contextually bound by subgroups, such as
with a business that is operated by traditional Muslims or environmental
activists. In these cases, the individual businesses may be bound by the
obligations of their subgroups, but such obligations are contingent upon one's
association with these social subgroups. And, clearly, the obligations within
those subgroups are not binding on those outside the subgroups. If a business
does not belong to any subgroup, then its only moral obligations will be those
within the context of society at large, and these obligations are in the law.
Corporations that assume an obligation beyond the law, either in their corporate codes or in
practice, take on responsibilities that most outsiders would designate as
optional. A good example is found in the mission statement of Ben & Jerry's
Ice Cream, which includes the following:
Social
Mission -- To operate the company in a way that actively recognizes the central
role that business plays in the structure of society by initiating innovative
ways to improve the quality of life of a broad community -- local, national,
and international.
Consistent
with this mission, the highest paid employees of Ben & Jerry's would not
earn more than seven times more than the lowest paid full-time employees.
"We do this," they explain, "because we believe that most
American corporations overpay top management, and underpay entry-level
employees -- and because everyone who works at Ben & Jerry's is a major
contributor to our success." In spite of the merits of this pay scale
policy, it clearly lacks majority endorsement in our national social group, and
would not be a binding obligation. In fact, it is not even binding on Ben &
Jerry’s itself since, in recent years, Ben & Jerry’s had to abandon its own
ideal pay scale in an effort to attract a CEO with the right skills to expand
their company.
Strictly following this legal approach to
business ethics may indeed prompt businesses to do the right thing, as
prescribed by law. Nevertheless, there are two key problems with restricting
morality solely to what the law requires. First, even in the best legal
context, the law will lag behind our moral condemnation of certain
unscrupulous, yet legal business practices. For example, in the past, drug
companies could make exaggerated claims about the miraculous curative
properties of their products. Now government regulations prohibit any
exaggerated claims. Thus, prior to the enactment of a law, there will be a
period of time when a business practice will be deemed immoral, yet the
practice will be legal. This would be a continuing problem since changes in
products, technology, and marketing strategies would soon present new
questionable practices that would not be addressed by existing legislation. A
second problem with the law-based approach is that, at best, it applies only to
countries such as our own whose business-related laws are morally
conscientious. The situation may be different for some developing countries
with less sophisticated laws and regulatory agencies.
Deriving Business
Ethics from General Moral Obligations. The third approach to business
ethics is that morality must be introduced as a factor that is external from
both the profit motive and the law. This is the approach taken by most
philosophers who write on business ethics, and is expressed most clearly in the
following from a well known business ethics essay:
Proper
ethical behavior exists on a plane above the law. The law merely specifies the
lowest common denominator of acceptable behavior. (Gene Laczniak,
"Business Ethics: A Manager's Primer," 1983)
The
most convenient way to explore this approach is to consider the supra-legal
moral principles that philosophers commonly offer. Five fairly broad moral
principles suggested by philosophers are as follows:
Harm principle: businesses should
avoid causing unwarranted harm.
Fairness principle: business should
be fair in all of their practices.
Human rights principle: businesses
should respect human rights.
Autonomy principle: businesses
should not infringe on the rationally reflective choices of people.
Veracity principle: businesses
should not be deceptive in their practices.
The
attraction of these principles is that they appeal to universal moral notions
that no one would reasonably reject. But, the problem with these principles is
that they are too general. These principles do not tell us specifically what
counts as harm, unfairness, or a violation of human rights. Does all damage to
the environment constitute harm? Does it violate an employee's right to privacy
if an employer places hidden surveillance cameras in an employee lounge area?
Does child-oriented advertising mislead children and thus violate the principle
of veracity?
The
above principles are abstract in nature. That is, they broadly mandate against
harm, and broadly endorse autonomy. Because they are abstract, they will be
difficult to apply to concrete situations and consequently not give clear
guidance in complex situations. An alternative approach is to forget the
abstract, and focus instead on concrete situations that affect the particular
interests of consumers, workers, stockholders, or the community. The recent
stakeholder approach to business ethics attempts to do this systematically. It
may be expressed in the following:
Stakeholder principle: businesses
should consider all stakeholders' interests that are affected by a business
practice.
A
stakeholder is any party affected by a business practice, including employees,
suppliers, customers, creditors, competitors, governments, and communities.
Accordingly, the stakeholder approach to business ethics emphasizes that we
should map out of the various parties affected by a business practice. But this
approach is limited since proponents of this view give us no clear formula for
how to prioritize the various interests once we map them out. Should all
stakeholders' interests be treated equally – from the largest stockholder down
to the garbage man who empties the factory dumpster? Probably no defenders of
the stakeholder approach would advocate treating all interests equally.
Alternatively, should the stockholders' interests have special priority? If we
take this route, then the stakeholder principle is merely a revision of the
profit principle.
Another
way of looking at concrete moral obligations in business is to list them issue
by issue. This is the strategy behind corporate codes of ethics that address
specific topics such as confidentiality of corporate information, conflicts of
interest, bribes, and political contributions. Consider the following issues
from Johnson and Johnson's Credo:
We
are responsible to our employees, the men and women who work with us throughout
the world. Everyone must be considered as an individual. We must respect their
dignity and recognize their merit. They must have a sense of security in their
jobs. Compensation must be fair and adequate, and working conditions clean,
orderly and safe. We must be mindful of ways to help our employees fulfill
their family responsibilities.
Although
corporate codes of ethics are often viewed cynically as attempts to foster good
public relations or to reduce legal liability, a corporate code of ethics is a
reasonable model for understanding how we should articulate moral principles and
introduce them into business practice. The practical advantage of this approach
is that it directly stipulates the morality of certain action types, without
becoming ensnared in the problem of deriving particular actions from more
abstract principles, such as the harm principle. But, the limitation of the
corporate code model is that the principles offered will appear to be merely
rules of prudence or good manners unless we can establish their distinctly
moral character. And this requires relying on more general principles of ethic
described above, which, we’ve seen, comes with its own set of problems.
Conclusion. We’ve looked at three approaches to business ethics, and
we’ve seen that all three have limitations. If we hope to find an approach to
business ethics that is free from conceptual problems, we will not likely find
any. Ethics is a complex subject and its history is filled with diverse
theories that are systematically refuted by rival theories. So, we should
expect to find controversies when applying ethics to the specific practices of
business. However, following any of the above three approaches to business
ethics will bring us closer to acceptable moral behavior than we might
otherwise be. Close attention to one’s profit motive and the moral interests of
consumers might in fact generate some morally responsible business decisions.
We can indeed find additional moral guidance by looking at the laws that apply
specifically to businesses. In gray areas of moral controversy that are not
adequately addressed profit motives and the law, we can turn for guidance to a
variety of general and specific moral principles.
In addition to the above three approaches to
business ethics, it also helps to examine stories of businesses that have been
morally irresponsible. By citing specific cases deceptive advertising,
environmental irresponsibility, or unsafe products, we can learn by example
what we should not do. Such cases often reveal blatantly crude, insensitive, or
reckless attitudes of businesses, which we can view as warning signs of
unethical conduct.
537, Varghese Plaza,
1st Floor, Vetturnimadam,
Nagercoil, K.K.Dist.
Ph: 04652-224337
Cell: 9500946903
Email : anitpromoters@gmail.com
Website: www.anitpromoters.com
Great blog.and one thing you know about Etown tirunelveli.Its a leading Local Search Engine. Find the most comprehensive local business information and services in nellai.
ReplyDelete